Marys Medicine

 

Neurohumanitiestudies.eu

Neuroaesthetics: A Coming of Age Story ■ Neuroaesthetics is gaining momentum. At this early junc- gence of experimental neuroaesthetics. I then suggest a few areas ture, it is worth taking stock of where the field is and what lies within neuroaesthetics that might be pursued profitably. Finally, I ahead. Here, I review writings that fall under the rubric of neuro- raise some challenges for the field. These challenges are not aesthetics. These writings include discussions of the parallel or- unique to neuroaesthetics. As neuroaesthetics comes of age, it ganizational principles of the brain and the intent and practices of might take advantage of the lessons learned from more mature artists, the description of informative anecdotes, and the emer- domains of inquiry within cognitive neuroscience. ■ within the last century, isolate and enhance different visual What does neuroscience have to offer aesthetics? Neuro- attributes. For example, Matisse emphasized color and aesthetics, as a field, is gathering force (Skov & Vartanian, Calder emphasized motion. Zeki suggests that artists en- 2009). As it grows, the field faces the challenge of being deavor to uncover important distinctions in the visual both true to its scientific roots and relevant to aesthetics.
world and discover visual modules that are segregated The term aesthetics is used broadly to encompass the per- functionally and anatomically within the brain.
ception, production, and response to art, as well as inter- Parallelism claims point to the fact that artists are ex- actions with objects and scenes that evoke an intense perts of visual representations and part of their magic lies feeling, often of pleasure. I focus on visual aesthetics, in their creative expression of this expertise. For example, although the principles also apply to music, dance, and lit- Cavanagh (2005) also shows that images in paintings often erature. The term neuroaesthetics is also used broadly as a violate the physics of shadows, reflections, colors, and con- domain that has something to do with properties of the tours. Rather than follow physical properties of the world, brain as it engages in aesthetics. I describe the kinds of these painters reflect perceptual shortcuts used by our writings that fall under the rubric of neuroaesthetics and minds. Artists, in experimenting with forms of depiction, examine what, in my view, is needed for the field to mature discovered what psychologists and neuroscientists are as a science, particularly as an experimental science. I then now identifying as principles of perception. Livingstone point to some questions worth pursuing in the near future (2002) and Conway and Livingstone (2007) reveal how ar- and conclude with challenges for the field.
tists make use of complex interactions between differentcomponents of vision in creating visual effects in theirpaintings. Livingstone suggests that the shimmering qual- NEUROAESTHETIC WRITINGS ity of water or the sunʼs glow on the horizon seen in someimpressionist paintings (e.g., the sun and surrounding clouds in Monetʼs "Impression Sunrise") is produced by Writings on aesthetics by prominent neuroscientists high- isoluminant objects distinguishable only by color. This light parallels between properties of art and organizational strategy plays on the distinction between the dorsal (where) principles of the brain. Zeki (1999a, 1999b) should be and ventral (what) processing distinction (Ungerleider & credited for introducing neuroaesthetics into scientific dis- Mishkin, 1982). The dorsal stream is sensitive to differ- course. He exemplifies the parallelism approach and ar- ences in luminance, motion, and spatial location, whereas gues forcefully that no theory of aesthetics is complete the ventral stream is sensitive to simple form and color.
without an understanding of its neural underpinnings.
Isoluminant forms are processed by the ventral stream He suggested that the goals of the nervous system and but are not fixed with respect to motion or spatial location, of artists are similar. Both are driven to understand essen- as the dorsal stream does not process this information.
tial visual attributes of the world. The nervous system de- Thus, isoluminant forms are experienced as unstable or composes visual information into such attributes as color, shimmering. Conversely, because shape can be derived from luminance, and motion. Similarly, many artists, particularly luminance differences, she argues that artists can use con-trast to produce shapes, and leave color for expressive, rather University of Pennsylvania than descriptive, purposes. Livingstone highlights the way 2010 Massachusetts Institute of Technology Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 23:1, pp. 53–62 that combinatorial properties of visual attributes contrib- problems with their language, attention, and ability to make ute to our visual perception. Artists use these combina- decisions. Despite these alterations in comportment and torial properties to produce specific aesthetic effects.
cognition, Miller and Hou (2004) and Miller et al. (1998) Ramachandran and Hirstein (1999) proposed a set of discovered that some people with FTD develop a propen- perceptual principles that might underlie aesthetic experi- sity to produce art. They note that the art tends to be rea- ences. They emphasize the "peak shift" phenomenon as of- listic rather than abstract or symbolic. The art is most often fering insight into the aesthetics of abstract art by relying on visual and is highly detailed. The artists with FTD them- Tinbergenʼs (1954) work on this phenomenon. Tinbergen selves are intensely preoccupied with their art, suggesting observed that sea gull chicks beg for food from their that obsessive–compulsive traits acquired through their mothers by pecking on a red spot near the tip of the disease contributes to this artistic proclivity.
motherʼs beak. However, the chicks respond even more Other cases of acquired obsessive–compulsive personal- vigorously to a disembodied long thin stick with three red ity traits have resulted in remarkable artistic output. Sacks stripes near the end. Ramachandran and Hirstein propose (1995b) described Franco Magnani, an Italian painter in San that neural structures that evolved to respond to specific vi- Francisco. Magnani painted hundreds of realistic scenes of sual stimuli respond more vigorously (a shift in their peak Pontito, an Italian town where he grew up. After a febrile response) to underlying primitives of that form even when illness, which was probably an encephalitis, he began to the viewer is not aware of the primitive. Their hypothesis paint obsessively. Pontito was the only subject of his art.
is that artists producing abstracts make explicit use of Sacks speculated that Magnani had partial complex seizures these visual primitives in evoking aesthetic responses in and was, in part, demonstrating the obsessive personality disorder sometimes associated with temporal lobe epi- The parallelism approach to neuroaesthetics recognizes lepsy ( Waxman & Geschwind, 1975). However, instead of that the production and perception of art ought to con- being hypergraphic verbally, as is more common among form to principles of neural organization. Properties of art- such people, he was hypergraphic visually. In a similar vein, works and strategies used by artists have parallels in how Lythgoe, Polak, Kalmus, de Haan, and Khean Chong (2005) the nervous system apprehends and organizes its visual reported the case of a builder with a subarachnoid hemor- world. The question for brain–art parallelism is how to rhage, who became an obsessive artist after he recovered translate this starting point into programmatic research from the initial injury. He began to draw hundreds of with experiments testing falsifiable hypotheses.
sketches, mostly faces. He then moved to large-scale draw-ings, sometimes covering entire room, and confined his artto a few themes. The authors emphasize his perseverative Informative Anecdotes tendencies as critical to the emergence of his artistic skills.
A good example of informative anecdotes is observations We also reported obsessive painting practices in an ar- of the effects of neurological disease on the production of tist with Parkinsonʼs disease following treatment with do- art (Zaidel, 2005). The effect of brain damage on the capa- pamine agonists (Chatterjee, Hamilton, & Amorapanth, city to produce visual art stands in sharp contrast to its ef- fects on many other human capacities. Diseases of the A subset of autistic children produces striking visual brain can impair our ability to speak or comprehend lan- images (Sacks, 1995a). The most detailed description of guage, to coordinate movements, to recognize objects, to such a case was Nadia, as reported by Selfe (1977). Despite apprehend emotions, and to make logical decisions.
severe developmental abnormalities, Nadia had remark- Although diseases of the brain can certainly impair the abil- able drawing skills. By the age of 3 she was drawing life-like ity to produce art, in some instances, paradoxically, the art horses. She drew intensively for a few moments at a time, seems to improve. Elsewhere, I proposed that such para- always copying images. She also focused on specific kinds doxical improvements can be produced by a changing dis- of images like horses, of which she drew hundreds of ex- position to produce art, an enhanced visual vocabulary, amples. Although Nadiaʼs abilities were striking, she is not better descriptive accuracy, or enhanced expressivity unique. Autistic children with striking drawing skills seem (Chatterjee, 2006, 2009). Here, I outline the changes in to focus on specific subjects and draw them repeatedly.
disposition and enhanced expressivity produced by these These artists produce realistic images and tend to be "experiments of nature." preoccupied by specific themes. Although the neural basisfor obsessive–compulsive disorders is not completely un-derstood, it is associated with a dysfunction of orbito-frontal Acquired Disposition to Produce Art and medial-temporal cortices and fronto-striatal circuits Neurological disorders that produce obsessive–compulsive (Kwon et al., 2003; Ursu, Stenger, Shear, Jones, & Carter, traits can also dispose people to produce art. Such a change 2003; Saxena et al., 1999). Notably, in the cases described, in disposition to produce art is exemplified in a subset of these regions could have been damaged and posterior patients with fronto-temporal dementias (FTDs). FTDs occipito-temporal cortices were presumably intact. The can cause profound changes in personality. People with preservation of posterior cortices ensures that the neural FTD can be disorganized, socially disinhibited, and have substrates for recognizing and representing faces, places, Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience Volume 23, Number 1 and objects are preserved and are thus available to be the changes in specific attributes of the art of any person with subject of these artistsʼ obsessions.
brain damage. Charting such changes systematically will al-low us to identify the specificity of patterns of change thathappens to production of art following brain damage.
Enhanced Expressivity Among the most intriguing effects of brain damage on ar-tists is the class of phenomena in which the resulting art is surprisingly appealing. Right hemisphere damage can pro-duce left spatial neglect in which patients are unaware of the left side of space (Chatterjee, 2003). Artists with ne- An experimental research program in visual neuro- glect omit the left side of images that they draw or paint aesthetics rests on two principles (Chatterjee, 2002, 2004a).
(Blanke, Ortigue, & Landis, 2003; Cantagallo & Sala, First, visual aesthetics, like vision in general, has multiple 1998; Halligan & Marshall, 1997; Schnider, Regard, Benson, components. Second, aesthetic experiences emerge from & Landis, 1993; Marsh & Philwin, 1987; Jung, 1974). As they a combination of responses to these different compo- recover from their neglect, their use of line may still be nents. The process by which humans visually recognize impaired. Two examples show how changed spatial repre- objects offers a framework from which to consider these sentations can produce highly regarded art. Lovis Corinth, components. Investigations can be focused on these com- an important German artist, suffered a right hemisphere ponents and on their properties in various combinations.
stroke in 1911. As he recovered, he resumed painting.
The nervous system processes visual information both His self portraits and portraits of his wife showed clear in hierarchical sequence and in parallel (Farah, 2000; Zeki, changes in style, with details on the left sometimes left 1993; Van Essen, Feleman, DeYoe, Ollavaria, & Knierman, out and textures on the left blended with the background.
1990). The sequential components of visual processing Alfred Kuhn characterized his later work as shifting him can be classified as early, intermediate, and late vision into the circle of great artists (quoted in Gardner, 1975).
(Marr, 1982). Early vision extracts simple elements from Heller (1994) reported the experience of Loring Hughes, the visual environment, such as color, luminance, shape, who after a right hemisphere stroke abandoned her pre- motion, and location (Livingstone & Hubel, 1987, 1988).
morbid style of depictive accuracy. Instead, she turned These simple elements are processed in different parts to her own imagination and emotions. The artistic commu- of the brain. Intermediate vision segregates some elements nity responded well to her new images. The critic Eileen and groups others together to form coherent regions in what Watkins described her work as now delivering "an emo- would otherwise be a chaotic and overwhelming sensory tional wallop," that was not present previously.
array (Ricci, Vaishnavi, & Chatterjee, 1999; Grossberg, Changes produced by left hemisphere damage are ex- Mingolla, & Ros, 1997; Vecera & Behrmann, 1997; Biederman emplified in the Bulgarian painter, Zlatio Boiyadjiev, and & Cooper, 1991). Late vision selects which of these coherent the Californian artist, Katherine Sherwood. Boiyadjievʼs regions to scrutinize and evokes memories from which ob- premorbid artistic style was natural and pictorial and he jects are recognized and meanings attached (Chatterjee, tended to use earth tones in his paintings. Following the 2003; Farah, 2000).
onset of his aphasia, Boiyadjievʼs paintings have been con- The hierarchical sequence of visual processing must be sidered richer, more colorful, and containing more fluid reflected in visual aesthetics (Chatterjee, 2004a; for related and energetic lines (Brown, 1977; Zaimov, Kitov, & Kolev, models that also incorporate broader contextual and cul- 1969). The imagery in his work became more inventive tural factors, see Jacobsen, 2006; Leder, Belke, Oeberst, and, at times, even bizarre and fantastical. Katherine & Augustin, 2004)). Any work of art can be decomposed Sherwood suffered a left hemisphere hemorrhagic stroke, into its early, intermediate, and late vision components.
which also left her with an aphasia and right-sided weak- Aesthetic perception can distinguish between form and ness ( Waldman, 2000). Premorbidly, her images were de- content (e.g., Woods, 1991; Russell & George, 1990), a dis- scribed as "highly cerebral." After her stroke, she felt that tinction demonstrated experimentally (Ishai, Fairhall, & she could not produce such images if she wanted. Her new Pepperell, 2007). Similarly, scientists observe that form is style has been described as "raw" and "intuitive," with large processed by early and intermediate vision, whereas con- irregular circular movements. She says her left hand enjoys tent is processed by later vision. Thus, the early vision fea- an ease and a grace with the brush that her right hand tures of an art object might be its color and its spatial never had, and describes it as "unburdened." location. These elements would be grouped together to These cases are but a few examples of the neuropsycho- form larger units in intermediate vision. Grouping creates logical effects of art (for comprehensive reviews, see "unity in diversity," a central notion of compositional Chatterjee, 2004b, 2009; Zaidel, 2005). The next step is to test the inferences made from these anecdotal observa- Beyond perception, two other aspects of aesthetics tions. To do so, we recently developed a tool, the Assessment are important. The first is the emotional response to an of Art Attributes (AAA) (Chatterjee, Widick, Sternschein, aesthetic image; the second is how aesthetic judgments Smith, & Bromberger, 2010). The AAA can quantify are made. The anterior medial temporal lobe, medial and orbito-frontal cortices, and subcortical structures have not been modified greatly by experience. Some com- mediate emotions in general, and reward systems in par- ponents of beauty are undoubtedly shaped further by cul- ticular (Berridge & Kringelbach, 2008; Breiter, Aharon, tural factors (Cunningham, Barbee, & Philhower, 2002), Kahneman, Dale, & Shizgal, 2001; OʼDoherty, Kringelbach, but the universal components are likely to have distinct Rolls, Hornack, & Andrews, 2001; Delgado, Nystrom, Fissell, Noll, & Fiez, 2000; Elliott, Friston, & Dolan, 2000; Schultz, Several studies report that attractive faces activate neural Dayans, & Montague, 1997). Aesthetic judgments about circuitry involved in reward systems, including orbito- stimuli, as measured by preference ratings, are likely to en- frontal cortex, the nucleus accumbens, the ventral stria- gage widely distributed circuits, most importantly, dorso- tum (Ishai, 2007; Kranz & Ishai, 2006; OʼDoherty et al., lateral frontal and medial frontal cortices. The general 2003; Aharon et al., 2001; Kampe, Frith, Dolan, & Frith, point is that visual neuroaesthetics, like most complex bio- 2001), and the amygdala ( Winston, OʼDoherty, Kilner, logical systems, is hierarchical and can be decomposed Perrett, & Dolan, 2007). These regional activations are in- into stable component subsystems (Simon, 1962). This terpreted as reflecting emotional valences attached to at- hierarchical organization is precisely what makes experi- tractive faces (Senior, 2003). The particular emotional mental approaches to aesthetics possible.
valences are those involved in the expectation of rewards I have emphasized a cognitive neuroscience framework and the satisfaction of appetites. The idea that attractive for experimental neuroaesthetics. Another overarching faces are rewarding stimuli, at least for men, is evident be- framework to think about aesthetics comes from evolu- haviorally. Heterosexual men discount higher future re- tionary theorists. They make three kinds of arguments.
wards for smaller immediate rewards with attractive First, beauty serves as a proxy for health and vigor in mate female faces ( Wilson & Daly, 2004). Presumably, these pat- selection. Second, beautiful objects are those that are com- terns of neural activation reflect ways in which attractive plex and yet are processed efficiently. And third, art mak- faces influence mate selection (Ishai, 2007; Kranz & Ishai, ing and appreciation serves an important ritualistic function that enhances social cohesion. Space limitations Perceptual features of faces, such as averageness, sym- do not allow an adequate consideration of evolutionary metry, the structure of cheekbones, the relative size of the perspectives on beauty and art (see Brown & Dissanayake, lower half of the face, and the width of the jaw, influence 2009; Cela-Conde et al., 2009; Dissanayake, 2008; Zaidel, peopleʼs judgments of facial beauty (Penton-Voak et al., 2005; Grammer, Fink, Moller, & Thornhill, 2003; Penton- 2001; Enquist & Arak, 1994; Grammer & Thornhill, 1994).
Voak et al., 2001; Etcoff, 1999; Rentschler, Jüttner, Unzicker, Winston et al. (2007) found that left posterior occipito- & Landis, 1999; Thornhill & Gangestad, 1999; Zahavi & temporal activity was enhanced by facial attractiveness.
Zahavi, 1997; Symons, 1979 for relevant discussions). Ulti- We conducted a study to examine the extent to which mately, evolutionary and cognitive neuroscience approaches facial attractiveness is apprehended automatically. Partici- to aesthetics are likely to converge in informative ways.
pants judged the attractiveness or matched the identity ofpairs of faces. Attractiveness judgments evoked neural ac-tivity within a distributed network involving ventral visual association cortices and parts of dorsal posterior parietal Beauty is central to most peopleʼs concept of aesthetics and prefrontal cortices (Chatterjee, Thomas, Smith, & ( Jacobsen, Buchta, Kohler, & Schroger, 2004). Of course, Aguirre, 2009). We inferred that the parietal, medial, and not all art is beautiful and artists do not always intend to dorsolateral frontal activations represented neural corre- produce beautiful things. However, beauty remains a cen- lates of the attention and decision-making components tral concept in discussions of aesthetic experiences. Un- of this task. We also found positively correlated activity derstanding the neural basis of the perception of and within the insula and negatively correlated activations response to beauty might give us insight into the percep- within anterior and posterior cingulate cortex. We inferred tion of and response to visual art. Facial beauty has re- that these patterns represent the emotional responses to ceived most attention in cognitive neuroscience.
attractiveness. Importantly, when subjects matched the The response to facial beauty is likely to be deeply en- identity of faces, attractiveness continued to evoke neural coded in our biology. Cross-cultural judgments of facial responses in ventral visual areas. This neural response was beauty are quite consistent (Etcoff, 1999; Perrett, May, & of a strength that was indistinguishable from the response Yoshikawa, 1994; Jones & Hill, 1993). Adults and children when participants considered beauty explicitly. We in- within and across cultures agree in their judgments of fa- ferred that this ventral occipital region responds to beauty cial attractiveness (Langlois et al., 2000), suggesting that universal principles of facial beauty exist. Infants look longer Facial attractiveness has pervasive social effects beyond at attractive faces within a week of being born, and the ef- its specific role in mate selection (Palermo & Rhodes, fects of facial attractiveness on infantsʼ gaze generalize 2007; Olson & Marshuetz, 2005). Attractive individuals across race, sex and age by 6 months (Slater et al., 1998; are considered intelligent, honest, pleasant, natural lead- Langlois, Ritter, Roggman, & Vaughn, 1991). Thus, the dis- ers (Ritts, Patterson, & Tubbs, 1992; Lerner, Lerner, Hess, position to engage attractive faces is present in brains that & Schwab, 1991; Kenealy, Frude, & Shaw, 1988), and are Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience Volume 23, Number 1 viewed as having socially desirable traits, such as strength beauty and complexity of the images evoked activity within and sensitivity (Dion, Berscheid, & Walster, 1972). The cas- orbito-frontal cortex. In a follow-up study using the same cade of neural events that bias social decisions is likely to stimuli (Hofel & Jacobsen, 2007), they found that beauty be triggered by an early perceptual response to attractive- generated a lateral positive evoked potential in a temporal ness. We proposed that neural activity within ventral visual window between 360 and 1225 msec.
cortices in automatic response to facial attractiveness One might be disheartened that these studies inves- serves as the initial trigger for this cascade (Chatterjee tigating aesthetics, report inconsistent patterns of activa- et al., 2009).
tion. Nadal, Munar, Capo, Rosselo, and Cela-Conde (2008)propose that these seemingly varied results of these studiesare compatible with the general model (Chatterjee, 2004a), linking aesthetics to the neuroscience of visual and affective A few studies have used art to examine the neural localiza- processing as well as reward systems and decision-making.
tion of aesthetic processes. Although the goals in these stud- Engaging visual properties of paintings increases activ- ies are similar, their experimental approaches differ and ity within ventral visual cortices ( Vartanian & Goel, 2004).
the results, at first glance, appear quite varied. Kawabata Aesthetic judgments activate parts of dorsolateral prefrontal and Zeki (2004) asked participants to rate abstract, still life, and medial prefrontal cortices ( Jacobsen et al., 2005; Cela- landscape, or portrait paintings as beautiful, neutral, or Conde et al., 2004). In addition, emotional responses to ugly. Not surprisingly, they found that the pattern of activ- these stimuli activate orbito-frontal ( Jacobsen et al., 2005; ity within ventral visual cortex varied depending on Kawabata & Zeki, 2004) as well as anterior cingulate cortices whether subjects were looking at portraits, landscapes, (de Tommaso, Sardaro, & Livrea, 2008; Kawabata & Zeki, or still lifes. In orbito-frontal (BA 11) cortex, they found 2004; Vartanian & Goel, 2004).
greater activity for beautiful than for ugly or neutral stimuli.
In anterior cingulate (BA 32) and left parietal cortex FUTURE DIRECTIONS (BA39), they found greater activity for beautiful than forneutral stimuli. Only activity within orbito-frontal cortex in- As neuroaesthetics moves forward, several domains could creased with the beauty of all the painting types and the be pursued profitably. Here, I suggest three: explorations authors interpreted this activity as representing the neural of the relationship of perception to aesthetic experiences, underpinnings of the aesthetic emotional experience.
the nature of aesthetic judgment, and characterizing the Vartanian and Goel (2004) used images of representa- aesthetic reward.
tional and abstract paintings in an fMRI study. They foundthat activity within the occipital gyri bilaterally and the left The Relationship of Perception to anterior cingulate increased with preference ratings. They Aesthetic Experiences also found that activity within the right caudate decreasedas preference ratings decreased. Representational paint- As described above, visual art can be decomposed into dis- ings evoked more activity within the occipital poles, the tinct attributes such as color, line, texture, and form. Prom- precuneus, and the posterior middle temporal gyrus than ising questions for empirical research include a better did abstract paintings.
understanding of how these visual perceptual attributes Cela-Conde et al. (2004) used magnetoencephalogra- contribute to the aesthetic experience. Can we measure phy to record event potentials when participants viewed the contributions of these attributes? Some properties of images of artworks and photographs. Participants judged visual displays can be described with exquisite mathe- whether or not the images were beautiful. Beautiful matical precision (Graham & Field, 2007; Redies, 2007).
images evoked greater neural activity than not beautiful These quantifiable parameters might also be used in neuro- images over left dorsolateral prefrontal cortex with a la- tency of 400–1000 msec. The authors infer that this region How much of the aesthetic experience resides in a per- is involved in making aesthetic judgments.
ceptual experience and how much resides in the emo- Jacobsen, Schubotz, Hofel, and von Cramon (2005) tional response to artwork? Paintings of landscapes are used a different strategy to investigate the neural corre- likely to activate the parahippocampus, still lifes lateral oc- lates of beauty in an fMRI study. Rather than use actual art- cipital cortex, and portraits the fusiform gyrus. Does works as their stimuli, they used a set of geometric shapes beauty modify these activations further? Perhaps these re- designed in the laboratory. Participants judged whether sponses simply reflect category-specific activations evoked the images were beautiful or whether the images were by perception itself and the aesthetic work is done within symmetric. Participants found symmetric patterns more reward systems. However, many feel that we perceive beautiful than nonsymmetric ones. Aesthetic judgments, beautiful objects more vividly than nonbeautiful objects.
more than symmetry judgments, activated medial frontal Some studies show neural responses to beauty within ven- cortex (BA 9/10), the precuneus, and ventral prefrontal tral occipito-temporal cortex. Does ventral visual cortex cortex (BA 44/47). The left intraparietal sulcus was con- contain general "visual beauty detectors"? Because people jointly active for symmetry and beauty judgments. Both are inclined to look longer at beautiful things, are such ventral visual activations a consequence of attention or is not clear from the experiment, it demonstrates that the there an independent aesthetic factor that modulates same object, when viewed under different conditions, neural activity? The relationship of attention and aesthetic can evoke different neural responses.
perception remains to be sorted out.
Fairhall and Ishai (2008), Wiesmann and Ishai (2008), Characterizing the Aesthetic "Reward" and Yago and Ishai (2006) have used paintings as stimulito study object recognition and recall. In these studies, they Beauty is a critically important aspect of how most peo- find activations in limbic and prefrontal regions, suggesting ple think of aesthetics ( Jacobsen et al., 2004). However, that emotional and reward systems are activated automati- aesthetics is not confined to beauty. Some artwork is spe- cally even though participants are not making evaluations.
cifically designed to be provocative and disturbing. Ulti- The apparent automaticity of our response to beauty or to mately, a comprehensive program in neuroaesthetics art is an area that invites further investigation.
would incorporate motivations in the creation of and the One could also investigate the relationship of percep- response to art that engage emotional systems beyond tion to aesthetics in brain-damaged people. Some people pleasurable reward systems.
with brain damage probably do not perceive art in the With respect to pleasure evoked by beauty or art, the same way that non-brain-damaged individuals do, and imaging studies reviewed here implicate orbito-frontal their emotional responses to artwork may very well differ cortex, the anterior and posterior cingulate, the ventral from those of people without brain damage. Such neuro- striatum including the nucleus accumbens, the caudate, psychological investigations of aesthetic perception to date and the amygdala as mediating the emotional response to are nonexistent.
beauty or to artwork. Presumably, these structures differ intheir functions. We need a better sense of how the orches-tration of activity within these structures contributes to an The Nature of Aesthetic Judgment overall emotional aesthetic (Biederman & Vessel, 2006).
Recent cognitive neuroscience methods probe individual Evolutionary arguments for the importance of beauty of- differences. As these methods continue to develop, they ten emphasize its importance in mate selection. Mate se- could also be used to examine individual differences lection is a utilitarian goal and the argument is that the in aesthetic sensitivities. Aesthetic sensitivity has been re- features that signal a desirable mate are the features we re- ferred to as a "T-factor", for taste (Eysenck & Hawker, gard as beautiful. This utilitarian goal is at odds with an idea 1994; Eysenck, 1941). People can also develop taste with proposed in the 18th century (Kant, 1790/1987) that the training. Behavioral studies show differences in the way aesthetic attitude is one of "disinterested interest." On this that art-experienced individuals and art-naïve individuals view, aesthetic objects give pleasure without evoking addi- engage with works of art (Locher, Stappers, & Overbeeke, tional desires. Stated differently, what distinguishes the 1999; Hekkert & Van Wieringen, 1996). Understanding the neural response to an aesthetic experience from other re- neural basis for taste and the ways aesthetic judgment warding experiences? Could neuroscience contribute to might be modified with training would be of great interest.
an understanding of disinterested interest? The studies conducted thus far suggest that parts of Berridge and Kringelbach (2008) and Wyvell and Berridge dorsolateral and medial prefrontal cortex are involved in (2000) draw a distinction between "liking" and "wanting".
making aesthetic judgments. These studies do not sort out Liking seems to be mediated by the nucleus accumbens whether these brain activations are specific to aesthetic shell and the ventral pallidum mediated by opioid and judgments or are part of neural systems that make judg- GABAerigic neurotransmitter systems. By contrast, the ments regardless of the domain under consideration. We mesolimbic dopaminergic system, which includes the nu- do not know if aesthetic judgments engage neural circuits cleus accumbens core, might mediate wanting. Cortical that are not engaged in other judgments.
structures, such as the cingulate and orbito-frontal cortex, Another issue around aesthetic judgments is the institu- may contribute further to conscious modulations of these tional context in which art is usually viewed. For example, liking and wanting experiences. This liking/wanting dis- Leder et al. (2004) argued that the same object is ap- tinction is made in a rodent model with experiments prehended and evaluated differently when viewed "as art- using sweet and bitter tasting stimuli. Whether the liking/ work." Recently, Cupchik, Vartanian, Crawley, and Mikulis wanting distinction generalizes to humans or to visual stim- (2009) showed differences in brain activations when par- uli remains to be seen. However, one might test the hy- ticipants looked at art paintings in an "objective and pothesis that a self-contained reward system exists and detached" manner than in a "subjective and engaged" forms the basis for aesthetic disinterested interest.
manner with an emphasis on experiencing the moodevoked by the paintings. They found greater activity in left lateral prefrontal cortex in the latter condition, which theyregard as aesthetic, than when participants looked at paint- These are early days in the neuroscience of visual aesthet- ings in a detached manner. Although the cognitive mech- ics. With a field so young, development in any direction anism underlying this difference in activation patterns is would be an advance. However, I suggest that practitioners Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience Volume 23, Number 1 of neuroaesthetics might keep the following challenges in world (Fairhall & Ishai, 2008; Wiesmann & Ishai, 2008; mind: risks of reduction, distinguishing investigations prob- Yago & Ishai, 2006). This line of work can be distinguished ing the brain from those probing aesthetics, and adding from those studies that use neuroscience to test hypoth- value to our understanding of aesthetics using neuroscience.
eses about the nature of aesthetics.
Fechner (1860), a century and a half ago, made the dis- tinction between an outer psychophysics and an inner Risks of Reduction psychophysics. Outer psychophysics is the study of the re-lationship between psychology and the physical proper- Experimental neuroaesthetics needs to conform to the con- ties of stimuli. This kind of study has been the thrust of straints of any experimental science. That is, experiments empirical aesthetics ever since. Inner psychophysics is need to be motivated by general frameworks and to test fal- the study of the relationship between psychology and sifiable hypotheses. Such experimental work would analyze the physical (or physiological) properties of the brain.
specific components of the broader universe of Fechner recognized that an inner psychophysics might aesthetics to simplify the domain needs in a way that allows be possible eventually. Neuroscience technologies such experimental control. Cognitive neuroscience studies of lan- as fMRI, ERPs, and transcranial magnetic stimulation now guage, emotion, and decision-making are models of this ap- provide the means of pursuing an inner psychophysics.
proach. Further, although qualitative analyses can certainly The nature of the triangular relationships among psy- provide important empirical information, quantification chology, outer physics, and inner physics could be made more easily provides ways to test hypotheses rigorously.
explicit. Conducting research that probes the relationship The risk of decomposition and quantification is that re- between outer and inner physics without direct recourse duction attenuates the very thing we are most interested in to psychology is possible. Here properties of objects, pos- studying. Take the example of the aesthetic responses to sibly aesthetic objects, would be/are used to probe the beauty. Experimental aesthetics often addresses this issue properties of the brain. In such experiments, finely charac- by obtaining preference ratings from participants. One terized stimuli are related to the spatial and temporal re- might ask methodological questions about whether sponse properties of neurons. Thus, one might find that forced-choice approaches or Likert-scale ratings are a the lateral occipital complex responds parametrically to more stable measure of peopleʼs preferences. One might some physical properties of objects, important informa- ask whether judgments of interestingness are the same as tion in its own right. The unanswered psychophysical judgments of preference. Or one might explore the rela- question would be, do lateral occipital complex neurons tionship of complexity to either preference or to interest.
simply serve a classification function, distinguishing be- These are legitimate and important questions to be pur- tween objects and other visual stimuli like faces and sued. However, the pursuit of such questions might easily places, or do they also serve an evaluative function, being obscure the basic question of how preference is related to tuned to whether the configuration of objects are appeal- aesthetic experience. Is preference a diluted version of ing as in the rich tradition of still life paintings? To answer the former? Or are deeply moving aesthetic experiences this question, researchers would use the brain to probe qualitatively different than those assessed in the laboratory the psychology of aesthetics rather than using aesthetic with preference ratings? What do neuroscientists make of objects to probe properties of the brain.
notions such as "the sublime?" The sublime is an emo- A danger in experiments designed to examine the rela- tional experience mentioned frequently in aesthetics tionship between inner and outer physics is that of making (Kant, 1790/1987), but one that has, so far, had little trac- inferences about the underlying psychology without ade- tion in affective neuroscience. Reducing components of quate investigation of the relevant behavior. This general aesthetics to quantifiable measures risks inviting the pro- problem is recognized in cognitive neuroscience as the re- verbial problem of looking for the dropped coin under the verse inference problem (Poldrack, 2006), where one uses lamp because that is where things are visible, even if the the location of neural activation to infer the underlying psy- coin was dropped elsewhere. This problem is true for ex- chological process. Such an inference is valid as a conclu- perimental aesthetics in general, not just neuroaesthetics.
sion if this area is engaged in only one psychologicalprocess. Unfortunately, such one-to-one correspondencesbetween neural activation and psychological process are Distinguishing Investigations Probing the Brain rare in the brain. Findings of localized activations to specific from Those Probing Aesthetics stimuli more often generate hypotheses about the mental Art can be used to probe properties of the brain. Because processes involved, rather than confirm these hypotheses.
brain systems devoted to aesthetics are complex and orga-nized hierarchically, processing art potentially provides a Adding Value to Our Understanding unique window into the interactions of various subsys- of Aesthetics Using Neuroscience tems. For example, abstract paintings can be used as aprobe to investigate how the brain deals with indetermi- This issue, in my view, is the most important challenge for nate visual stimuli and tries to make sense of its visual neuroaesthetics. If the goal is to understand aesthetics (as opposed to understanding the brain), what does neuro- Cantagallo, A., & Sala, S. D. (1998). Preserved insight in an artist aesthetics offer? When does neuroscience provide deeper with extrapersonal spatial neglect. Cortex, 34, 163–189.
Cavanagh, P. (2005). The artist as neuroscientist. Nature, 434, descriptive texture to our knowledge of aesthetics and when does it deliver added explanatory force? Knowing Cela-Conde, C. J., Ayala, F. J., Munar, E., Maestu, F., Nadal, M., that the pleasure of viewing a beautiful painting is corre- Capo, M. A., et al. (2009). Sex-related similarities and lated with activity within orbito-frontal cortex or the nucleus differences in the neural correlates of beauty. Proceedings accumbens adds biologic texture to our understanding of of the National Academy of Sciences, U.S.A., 106, 3847–3852.
the rewards of aesthetic experiences. However, it is not ob- Cela-Conde, C. J., Marty, G., Maestu, F., Ortiz, T., Munar, E., Fernandez, A., et al. (2004). Activation of the prefrontal vious that it, by itself, advances our understanding of the cortex in the human visual aesthetic perception.
psychological nature of that reward.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, U.S.A., For neuroscience to make important contributions to 101, 6321–6325.
aesthetics, the possibility of an inner psychophysics has Chatterjee, A. (2002). Universal and relative aesthetics: A to be taken seriously. That is, how do the physiological framework from cognitive neuroscience. Paper presentedat the International Association of Empirical Aesthetics, properties of the brain and the psychology of aesthetics August 4–8, 2002, Takarazuka, Japan.
relate to each other? More specifically, when does neu- Chatterjee, A. (2003). Neglect. A disorder of spatial attention.
roscience add something to the understanding of the psy- In M. DʼEsposito (Ed.), Neurological foundations of cognitive chology of aesthetics that cannot be discovered by neuroscience (pp. 1–26). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
behavioral studies alone? Chatterjee, A. (2004a). Prospects for a cognitive neuroscience of visual aesthetics. Bulletin of Psychology and the Arts, 4, These are early days in neuroaesthetics. The challenges mentioned here should not be construed as causes for Chatterjee, A. (2004b). The neuropsychology of visual artists.
pessimism. These challenges apply equally to the cognitive Neuropsychologia, 42, 1568–1583.
neuroscience of any complex domain. However, as neu- Chatterjee, A. (2006). The neuropsychology of visual art: roaesthetics comes of age, the field can be guided by the Conferring capacity. International Review of Neurobiology,74, 39–49.
lessons learned from investigations in more mature do- Chatterjee, A. (2009). Prospects for a neuropsychology of art.
mains, such as the cognitive neuroscience of memory, lan- In M. Skov & O. Vartanian (Eds.), Neuroaesthetics guage, and emotions.
(pp. 131–143). Amityville, NY: Baywood Publishing.
Chatterjee, A., Hamilton, R. H., & Amorapanth, P. X. (2006). Art produced by a patient with Parkinsonʼs disease. Behavioural Neurology, 17, 105–108.
Chatterjee, A., Thomas, A., Smith, S. E., & Aguirre, G. K. (2009).
I thank Lisa Santer for a critical review of an early version of this The neural response to facial attractiveness.
Neuropsychology, 23, 135–143.
Reprint requests should be sent to Anjan Chatterjee, Department Chatterjee, A., Widick, P., Sternschein, R., Smith, W. B., II, & of Neurology and Center for Cognitive Neuroscience, 3 West Bromberger, B. (2010). The assessment of art attributes.
Gates, 3400 Spruce Street, Philadelphia, PA 19104, or via e-mail: Empirical Studies of the Arts, 28, 207–222.
Conway, B. R., & Livingstone, M. S. (2007). Perspectives on science and art. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 17,476–482.
Cunningham, M., Barbee, A., & Philhower, C. (2002).
Dimensions of facial physical attractiveness: The intersection Aharon, I., Etcoff, N., Ariely, D., Chabris, C., OʼConnor, E., & of biology and culture. In G. Rhodes & L. Zebrowitz (Eds.), Breiter, H. (2001). Beautiful faces have variable reward value: Facial attractiveness. Evolutionary, cognitive, and social fMRI and behavioral evidence. Neuron, 32, 537–551.
perspectives (pp. 193–238). Westport, CT: Ablex.
Berridge, K., & Kringelbach, M. (2008). Affective Cupchik, G. C., Vartanian, O., Crawley, A., & Mikulis, D. J.
neuroscience of pleasure: Reward in humans and (2009). Viewing artworks: Contributions of cognitive control animals. Psychopharmacology, 199, 457–480.
and perceptual facilitation to aesthetic experience. Brain Biederman, I., & Cooper, E. (1991). Priming contour-deleted and Cognition, 70, 84–91.
images: Evidence for intermediate representations in visual de Tommaso, M., Sardaro, M., & Livrea, P. (2008). Aesthetic object recognition. Cognitive Psychology, 23, 393–419.
value of paintings affects pain thresholds. Consciousness and Biederman, I., & Vessel, E. A. (2006). Perceptual pleasure and Cognition, 17, 1152–1162.
the brain. American Scientist, 94, 247–253.
Delgado, M., Nystrom, L., Fissell, K., Noll, D., & Fiez, J. (2000).
Blanke, O., Ortigue, S., & Landis, T. (2003). Color neglect in Tracking the hemodynamic responses for reward and an artist. Lancet, 361, 264.
punishment. Journal of Neurophysiology, 84, 3072–3077.
Breiter, H., Aharon, I., Kahneman, D., Dale, A., & Shizgal, P.
Dion, K., Berscheid, E., & Walster, E. (1972). What is beautiful is (2001). Functional imaging of neural response to expectancy good. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 24, and experience of monetary gains and losses. Neuron, 30, Dissanayake, E. (2008). The arts after Darwin: Does art have Brown, J. (1977). Mind, brain, and consciousness. The an origin and adaptive function? In K. Zijlemans & W. van neuropsychology of cognition. New York: Academic Press.
Damme (Eds.), World art studies: Exploring concepts and Brown, S., & Dissanayake, E. (2009). The arts are more than approaches (pp. 241–263). Amsterdam: Valiz.
aesthetics: Neuroaesthetics as narrow aesthetics. In M. Skov Elliott, R., Friston, K., & Dolan, R. (2000). Dissociable neural & O. Vartanian (Eds.), Neuroaesthetics ( pp. 43–57).
responses in human reward systems. Journal of Amityville, NY: Baywood Publishing.
Neuroscience, 20, 6159–6165.
Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience Volume 23, Number 1 Enquist, M., & Arak, A. (1994). Symmetry, beauty and evolution.
Kawabata, H., & Zeki, S. (2004). Neural correlates of beauty.
Nature, 372, 169–172.
Journal of Neurophysiology, 91, 1699–1705.
Etcoff, N. (1999). Survival of the prettiest. New York: Anchor Kenealy, P., Frude, N., & Shaw, W. (1988). Influence of childrenʼs physical attractiveness on teacher expectations.
Eysenck, H. J. (1941). The empirical determination of an Journal of Social Psychology, 128, 373–383.
aesthetic formula. Psychological Review, 48, 83–92.
Kranz, F., & Ishai, A. (2006). Face perception is modulated Eysenck, H. J., & Hawker, G. W. (1994). The taxonomy of visual by sexual preference. Current Biology, 16, 63–68.
aesthetic preferences: An empirical study. Empirical Studies Kwon, J., Kinm, J., Lee, D., Lee, J., Lee, D., Kim, M., et al. (2003).
of the Arts, 12, 95–101.
Neural correlates of clinical symptoms and cognitive Fairhall, S. L., & Ishai, A. (2008). Neural correlates of object dysfunctions in obsessive–compulsive disorder. Psychiatry indeterminacy in art compositions. Consciousness and Research, 122, 37–47.
Cognition, 17, 923–932.
Langlois, J., Kalakanis, L., Rubenstein, A., Larson, A., Hallam, M., Farah, M. (2000). The cognitive neuroscience of vision. Malden, & Smoot, M. (2000). Maxims or myths of beauty: A MA: Blackwell Publishers.
meta-analytic and theoretical review. Psychological Bulletin, Fechner, G. (1860). Elements of psychophysics (H. Adler, 126, 390–423.
Trans.). New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, Inc.
Langlois, J. H., Ritter, J. M., Roggman, L. A., & Vaughn, L. S.
Gardner, H. (1975). The shattered mind. The person after (1991). Facial diversity and infant preferences for attractive brain damage. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
faces. Developmental Psychology, 27, 79–84.
Graham, D. J., & Field, D. J. (2007). Statistical regularities of Leder, H., Belke, B., Oeberst, A., & Augustin, D. (2004). A art images and natural scenes: Spectra, sparseness and model of aesthetic appreciation and aesthetic judgments.
nonlinearities. Spatial Vision, 21, 149–164.
British Journal of Psychology, 95, 489–508.
Grammer, K., Fink, B., Moller, A. P., & Thornhill, R. (2003).
Lerner, R., Lerner, J., Hess, L., & Schwab, J. (1991). Physical Darwinian aesthetics: Sexual selection and the biology of attractiveness and psychosocial functioning among early beauty. Biological Review, 78, 385–407.
adolescents. Journal of Early Adolescence, 11, 300–320.
Grammer, K., & Thornhill, R. (1994). Human (Homo sapiens) Livingstone, M. (2002). Vision and art: The biology of seeing.
facial attractiveness and sexual selection: The role of New York: Abrams.
symmetry and averageness. Journal of Comparative Livingstone, M., & Hubel, D. (1988). Segregation of form, Psychology, 108, 233–242.
colour, movement, and depth: Anatomy, physiology, and Grossberg, S., Mingolla, E., & Ros, W. D. (1997). Visual brain perception. Science, 240, 740–749.
and visual perception: How does the cortex do perceptual Livingstone, M., & Hubel, D. H. (1987). Psychophysical grouping? Trends in Neurosciences, 20, 106–111.
evidence for separate channels for the perception of form, Halligan, P. W., & Marshall, J. C. (1997). The art of visual color, movement, and depth. Journal of Neuroscience, 7, neglect. Lancet, 350, 139–140.
Hekkert, P., & Van Wieringen, P. C. W. (1996). Beauty in the eye Locher, P. J., Stappers, P. J., & Overbeeke, K. (1999). An of expert and nonexpert beholders: A study in the appraisal empirical evaluation of the visual rightness theory of pictorial of art. American Journal of Psychology, 109, 389–407.
composition. Acta Psychologica, 103, 261–280.
Heller, W. (1994). Cognitive and emotional organization of Lythgoe, M., Polak, T., Kalmus, M., de Haan, M., & Khean the brain: Influences on the creation and perception of art.
Chong, W. (2005). Obsessive, prolific artistic output following In D. Zaidel (Ed.), Neuropsychology (pp. 271–292).
subarachnoid hemorrhage. Neurology, 64, 397–398.
New York: Academic Press.
Marr, D. (1982). Vision. A computational investigation into the Hofel, L., & Jacobsen, T. (2007). Electrophysiological indices human representation and processing of visual of processing aesthetics: Spontaneous or intentional information. New York: WH Freeman and Company.
processes? International Journal of Psychophysiology, Marsh, G. G., & Philwin, B. (1987). Unilateral neglect and 65, 20–31.
constructional apraxia in a right-handed artist with a left Ishai, A. (2007). Sex, beauty and the orbitofrontal cortex.
posterior lesion. Cortex, 23, 149–155.
International Journal of Psychophysiology, 63, 181–185.
Miller, B., & Hou, C. (2004). Portraits of artists: Emergence Ishai, A., Fairhall, S., & Pepperell, R. (2007). Perception, of visual creativity in dementia. Archives of Neurology, 61, memory and aesthetics of indeterminate art. Brain Research Bulletin, 73, 319–324.
Miller, B. L., Cummings, J., Mishkin, F., Boone, K., Prince, F., Jacobsen, T. (2006). Bridging the arts and sciences: A Ponton, M., et al. (1998). Emergence of artistic talent in framework for the psychology of aesthetics. Leonardo, 39, frontotemporal dementia. Neurology, 51, 978–982.
Nadal, M., Munar, E., Capo, M. A., Rosselo, J., & Cela-Conde, Jacobsen, T., Buchta, K., Kohler, M., & Schroger, E. (2004).
C. J. (2008). Towards a framework for the study of the neural The primacy of beauty in judging the aesthetics of objects.
correlates of aesthetic preference. Spatial Vision, 21, Psychological Reports, 94, 1253–1260.
Jacobsen, T., Schubotz, R., Hofel, L., & von Cramon, D. (2005).
OʼDoherty, J., Kringelbach, M., Rolls, E., Hornack, J., & Brain correlates of aesthetic judgments of beauty.
Andrews, C. (2001). Abstract reward and punishment Neuroimage, 29, 276–285.
representations in the human orbitofrontal cortex. Nature Jones, D., & Hill, K. (1993). Criteria of facial attractiveness in Neuroscience, 4, 95–102.
five populations. Human Nature, 4, 271–296.
OʼDoherty, J., Winston, J., Critchley, H., Perret, D., Burt, D., & Jung, R. (1974). Neuropsychologie und neurophysiologie Dolan, R. (2003). Beauty in a smile: The role of orbitofrontal des konturund formsehens in zeichnerei und malerei. In cortex in facial attractiveness. Neuropsychologia, 41, H. Weick (Ed.), Pyschopathologie Mususcher Gestaltungen (pp. 27–88). Stuttgart: FK Shattauer.
Olson, I., & Marshuetz, C. (2005). Facial attractiveness is Kampe, K., Frith, C., Dolan, R., & Frith, U. (2001). Reward value appraised in a glance. Emotion, 5, 498–502.
of attractiveness and gaze. Nature, 413, 589.
Palermo, R., & Rhodes, G. (2007). Are you always on my mind? Kant, I. (1790/1987). Critique of judgment ( W. S. Pluhar, A review of how face perception and attention interact.
Trans.). Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.
Neuropsychologia, 45, 75–92.
Penton-Voak, I. S., Jones, B. C., Little, A. C., Baker, S., Thornhill, R., & Gangestad, S. W. (1999). Facial attractiveness.
Tiddeman, B., Burt, D. M., et al. (2001). Symmetry, sexual Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 3, 452–260.
dimorphism in facial proportions and male facial Tinbergen, N. (1954). Curious naturalist. New York: Basic attractiveness. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, Series B, Biological Sciences, 268, 1617–1623.
Ungerleider, L. G., & Mishkin, M. (1982). Two cortical visual Perrett, D. I., May, K. A., & Yoshikawa, S. (1994). Facial shape systems. In D. J. Ingle, M. A. Goodale, & R. J. W. Mansfield and judgements of female attractiveness. Nature, 368, (Eds.), Analysis of visual behavior (pp. 549–586).
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Poldrack, R. A. (2006). Can cognitive processes be inferred Ursu, S., Stenger, V., Shear, M., Jones, M., & Carter, C. S. (2003).
from neuroimaging data? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10, Overactive action monitoring in obsessive–compulsive disorder. Psychological Science, 14, 347–353.
Ramachandran, V. S., & Hirstein, W. (1999). The science of art: Van Essen, D. C., Feleman, D. J., DeYoe, E. A., Ollavaria, J., & A neurological theory of aesthetic experience. Journal of Knierman, J. (1990). Modular and hierarchical organization Consciousness Studies, 6, 15–51.
of extrastriate visual cortex in the macaque monkey. Cold Redies, C. (2007). A universal model of esthetic perception Springs Harbor Symposia on Quantitative Biology, 55, based on the sensory coding of natural stimuli. Spatial Vision, 21, 97–117.
Vartanian, O., & Goel, V. (2004). Neuroanatomical correlates Rentschler, I., Jüttner, M., Unzicker, A., & Landis, T. (1999).
of aesthetic preference for paintings. NeuroReport, 15, Innate and learned components of human visual preference.
Current Biology, 9, 665–671.
Vecera, S., & Behrmann, M. (1997). Spatial attention does Ricci, R., Vaishnavi, S., & Chatterjee, A. (1999). A deficit of not require preattentive grouping. Neuropsychology, 11, preattentive vision: Experimental observations and theoretical implications. Neurocase, 5, 1–12.
Waldman, P. (2000, May 12, Friday). Master stroke: A tragedy Ritts, V., Patterson, M., & Tubbs, M. (1992). Expectations, transforms a right-handed artist into a lefty and a star. Wall impressions, and judgments of physically attractive students: Street Journal.
A review. Review of Educational Research, 62, 413–426.
Waxman, S., & Geschwind, N. (1975). The interictal behavior Russell, P. A., & George, D. A. (1990). Relationships between syndrome associated with temporal lobe epilepsy. Archives aesthetic response scales applied to paintings. Empirical of General Psychiatry, 32, 1580–1586.
Studies of the Arts, 8, 15–30.
Wiesmann, M., & Ishai, A. (2008). Recollection- and familiarity- Sacks, O. (1995a). Prodigies. In An anthropologist on Mars based decisions reflect memory strength. Frontiers in (pp. 188–243). New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Systems Neuroscience, 2, 1–9.
Sacks, O. (1995b). The landscape of his dreams. In An Wilson, M., & Daly, M. (2004). Do pretty women inspire men to anthropologist on Mars (pp. 153–187). New York: discount the future. Proceedings of the Royal Society of Alfred A. Knopf.
London, Series B, Biological Sciences, 271, 177–179.
Saxena, S., Brody, A., Maidment, K., Dunkin, J., Colgan, M., Winston, J., OʼDoherty, J., Kilner, J., Perrett, D., & Dolan, R.
Alborzian, S., et al. (1999). Localized orbitofrontal and (2007). Brain systems for assessing facial attractiveness.
subcortical metabolic changes and predictors of response Neuropsychologia, 45, 195–206.
to paroxetine treatment in obsessive–compulsive disorder.
Woods, W. A. (1991). Parameters of aesthetic objects: Applied Neuropsychopharmacology, 21, 683–693.
aesthetics. Empirical Studies of the Arts, 9, 105–114.
Schnider, A., Regard, M., Benson, D. F., & Landis, T. (1993).
Wyvell, C., & Berridge, K. (2000). Intra-accumbens Effect of a right-hemisphere stroke on an artistʼs amphetamine increases the conditioned incentive salience of performance. Neuropsychiatry, Neuropsychology, & sucrose reward: Enhancement of reward "wanting" without Behavioral Neurology, 6, 249–255.
enhanced "liking" or response reinforcement. Journal of Schultz, W., Dayans, P., & Montague, P. (1997). A neural Neuroscience, 20, 8122–8130.
substrate of prediction and reward. Science, 275, 1593–1599.
Yago, E., & Ishai, A. (2006). Recognition memory is modulated Selfe, L. (1977). Nadia. A case of extraordinary drawing by visual similarity. Neuroimage, 31, 807–817.
ability in an autistic child. New York: Academic Press.
Zahavi, A., & Zahavi, A. (1997). The handicap principle: Senior, C. (2003). Beauty in the brain of the beholder. Neuron, A missing piece of Darwinʼs puzzle. Oxford, UK: Oxford 38, 525–528.
University Press.
Simon, H. A. (1962). The architecture of complexity. Proceedings Zaidel, D. (2005). Neuropsychology of art. New York: of the American Philosophical Society, 106, 467–482.
Psychology Press.
Skov, M., & Vartanian, O. (Eds.) (2009). Neuroaesthetics.
Zaimov, K., Kitov, D., & Kolev, N. (1969). Aphasie chez un Amityville, NY: Baywood Publishing.
peintre. Encephale, 58, 377–417.
Slater, A., Schulenburg, C. V. D., Brown, E., Badenoch, M., Zeki, S. (1993). A vision of the brain. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Butterworth, G., Parsons, S., et al. (1998). Newborn infants prefer attractive faces. Infant Behavior and Development, Zeki, S. (1999a). Art and the brain. Journal of Consciousness 21, 345–354.
Studies, 6, 76–96.
Symons, D. (1979). The evolution of human sexuality. Oxford, Zeki, S. (1999b). Inner vision: An exploration of art and the UK: Oxford University Press.
brain. New York: Oxford University Press.
Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience Volume 23, Number 1 This article has been cited by:
1. Emily S. Cross, Luca F. Ticini. 2011. Neuroaesthetics and beyond: new horizons in applying the science of the brain to the art of dance. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences . []

Source: http://www.neurohumanitiestudies.eu/archivio/ChatterjeeNeuroaestheticsJOCN(1).pdf

Op-jeen150272 1.8

Journal of Economic Entomology Advance Access published September 5, 2015 Spray Toxicity and Risk Potential of 42 Commonly Used Formulations of Row Crop Pesticides to Adult Honey Bees (Hymenoptera: Apidae) YU CHENG ZHU,1,2 JOHN ADAMCZYK,3 THOMAS RINDERER,4 JIANXIU YAO,1 ROBERT DANKA,4 RANDALL LUTTRELL,1 AND JEFF GORE5 J. Econ. Entomol. 1–8 (2015); DOI: 10.1093/jee/tov269

about.abc.net.au

for the year ended 30 June 2012 ABC Charter and Duties of the Board ABC Board and Board Committees ABC Organisation, as at 30 June 2012 ABC Advisory Council ABC Code of Practice ABC Television Content Analysis ABC Radio Networks Content Analysis Overseas Travel Costs 10 Additional Reports Required by Legislation 22511 Promotion and Market Research 12 Work Health and Safety